The following is an edited transcript of Hans-Hermann Hoppe, The Libertarian Search for a Grand Historical Narrative (Part I) (PFS 2018). Published at Mises Wire, 11/5/2018 (a version also published in Vol. 24 (2020) of the Journal of Libertarian Studies). Video available here Hans-Hermann Hoppe, The Libertarian Search for a Grand Historical Narrative (Part I) (PFS 2018).
See also Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Progress According to Pinker (Part II) (PFS 2018) and Discussion Q&A, Dürr, van Dun, Hoppe (PFS 2018).
The Libertarian Quest for a Grand Historical Narrative
It is no secret that I am not a Hayekian. Still, I consider Hayek a great economist – not in the same league as Mises, but few if any economists are. Hayek’s fame in the public mind, however, has less to do with his economic writings but stems largely from his writings in political theory, and it is in this area where I consider Hayek as mostly deficient. Not even his system of definitions here is internally consistent. His excursions into the field of epistemology are quite ingenious, yet also here he falls short of the accomplishments of his teacher Mises. Nonetheless, owing to his wide-ranging interdisciplinary oeuvre, which contains a treasure trove of keen insights into many issues, I consider Hayek one of the 20th century’s outstanding intellectuals writing in the social sciences.
As a reflection of this esteem, Hayek was also quoted in the programmatic statement of the PFS:
“We must make the building of a free society once more an intellectual adventure, a deed of courage. What we lack is a liberal Utopia, a programme which seems neither a mere defence of things as they are nor a diluted kind of socialism, but a truly liberal radicalism which does not spare the susceptibilities of the mighty…, which is not too severely practical and which does not confine itself to what appears today as politically possible. We need intellectual leaders who are prepared to resist the blandishments of power and influence and who are willing to work for an ideal, however small may be the prospects of its early realization. They must be men who are willing to stick to principles and to fight for their full realization, however remote. … Unless we can make the philosophical foundations of a free society once more a living intellectual issue, and its implementation a task which challenges the ingenuity and imagination of our liveliest minds, the prospects of freedom are indeed dark. But if we can regain that belief in the power of ideas which was the mark of liberalism at its best, the battle is not lost.”
Hayek of course did not follow his own advice but ended up, in his political philosophy, with a mish-mash full of internally inconsistent compromises. Yet this does not mean that his plea for an uncompromising intellectual radicalism, which has been the purpose and become the hallmark of the PFS, is not worthwhile or correct.
But this shall not be my topic here. Rather, I want to speak about another important, if you will complementary insight of Hayek’s that can be found in the introduction he wrote for the collection of essays gathered in the book Capitalism and the Historians. Here, Hayek makes the point that while uncompromising intellectual radicalism is necessary as a source of energy and inspiration for the leaders of a liberal-libertarian movement, this is not sufficient to make for public appeal. Because the general public is not used to or incapable of abstract reasoning, high theory and intellectual consistency, but forms its political views and convictions on the basis of historical narratives, i.e. of prevailing interpretations of past events, and hence it is upon those who want to change things for a better, liberal-libertarian future to challenge and correct such interpretations and propose and promote alternative, revisionist historical narratives.
Let me quote from Hayek to this effect: “While the events of the past are the source of the experience of the human race, their opinions are determined not by the objective facts but by the records and interpretations to which they have access. … Historical myths have perhaps played nearly as great a role in shaping opinion as historical facts. … The influence which the writers of history thus exercise on public opinion is probably more immediate and extensive than that of the political theorists who launch new ideas. It seems as though even such new ideas reach wider circles usually not in their abstract form but as the interpretations of particular events. The historian is in this respect at least one step nearer to direct power over public opinion than is the theorist. … Most people, when being told that their political convictions have been affected by particular views on economic history, will answer that they never have been interested in it and never have read a book on the subject. This, however, does not mean that they do not, with the rest, regard as established facts many of the legends which at one time or another have been given currency by writers on economic history.”
The central theme of the mentioned book, edited by Hayek, is the revision of the still popular myth that it was the system of free market capitalism, at the time of the beginning of the so-called Industrial Revolution, around the early 1800s, which has been responsible for the economic misery that caused even little children having to work for 16 hours or more under atrocious conditions in mines or similarly uncomfortable work places; and that it was only due to the pressure of labor unions and government intervention into the economy by so-called “social policy” means and measures that this “inhumane” system of “capitalist exploitation” was gradually overcome and improved.
When first hearing this sad story, one would think that the immediate question coming to mind should be: why would any parent subject his child to such a treatment and hand it over to some evil capitalist exploiters? Did these children have a jolly good time before, strolling around in meadows and fields, healthy and with red cheeks, picking flowers, eating apples from apple trees, fishing and swimming in creeks, rivers and lakes, playing with their toys and attentively listening to their grandparents’ tales? In that case, what horrible people must these parents have been?! Merely asking these questions should be sufficient to realize that this story cannot be true. And in fact, as Hayek and his collaborators demonstrated, it is just about the opposite of the truth.
Until the Industrial Revolution, England and the rest of the world, for thousands of years, had lived under Malthusian conditions. That is, the supply of consumer goods provided by nature and by human production through means of intermediate tools and producer goods was not sufficient to ensure the survival of a growing population. Population growth exceeded the growth of production and any increases in productivity and hence, not only in England but everywhere, an “excess” of population regularly had to die off due to malnutrition, ill health and ultimately starvation. It was only with and since the Industrial Revolution that this situation fundamentally changed and the Malthusian trap was successively overcome, first in England, then in continental Europe and the European overseas dependencies and finally also in much of the rest of the world, so as to allow not only for a steadily growing population but an increasing population with continuously rising material standards of living. And this momentous achievement was the result of free market capitalism, or more precisely a combination and interplay of three factors. For one, the general security of private property; second, the low time preference, i.e., the ability and willingness of a growing number of people to delay immediate gratification so as to save for the future and accumulate an ever larger stock of capital goods; and third, the intelligence and ingenuity of a sufficient number of people to invent and engineer a steady stream of ever new, productivity enhancing tools and machines.
The parents of the poor children, who handed them over to the “evil capitalists” at the time of the Industrial Revolution were not bad parents, then, but like most parents everywhere who want the best for their children, they chose to do so, because they preferred their children alive, even if it was a miserable life, rather than dead. Contrary to still popular myth in leftist circles, then, capitalism did not cause misery, but it literally saved the lives of countless millions of people from death by starvation and gradually lifted them up from their previous state of abject poverty; and labor unions’ and governments’ so-called “social policies” did not help in this regard but hampered and retarded this process of gradual economic improvement and were and still are responsible for countless numbers of unnecessary deaths.
There are many other related, equally or even more absurd myths propagated by, to use Nicholas Taleb’s label, IYIs (intellectuals yet idiots) and widely believed by the general public: That you can legislate greater economic prosperity by simply passing minimum wage laws – but why, then, not legislate hourly wage rates of 100 or 1000 US-dollars, and why, then, is India, for instance, still a poor country? Are the ruling elites in India too dumb to know about this magic formula? Or else, that economic misery can be overcome by simply increasing monetary spending – but why, then, since everywhere nowadays governments can easily increase the quantity of paper money in practically unlimited amounts, is there still any poor person around?
Nor are such faulty historical narratives restricted only to economic history. Rather, much of what we have learned as the established truth from our standard history books about World War I and World War II, about the American and the French Revolution, about Hitler, Churchill, FDR or Napoleon, and on and on and on, also turns out faulty history: facts mixed in, whether intentional or unintentional, with hefty doses of fiction and fake.
Important as the revision of all these myths is, however, whether economic or otherwise, the greatest challenge for libertarians is to develop a grand historical narrative that is to counter and correct the so-called Whig theory of history that all ruling elites, everywhere and at all times, have tried to sell to the public: that is the view, that we live in the best of all times (and that they are the ones who guarantee that this stays so) and that the grand sweep of history, notwithstanding some ups and downs, has been one of more or less steady progress. This Whig theory of history, despite some setbacks motivated in particular by the experiences of the two disastrous world-wars during the first half of the 20th century, has again regained a predominant position in the public mind, as indicated by the success of such books as Francis Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man or, still more recently, Steven Pinker’s The Better Angels of our Nature and Enlightenment Now.
According to the proponents of this theory, what makes the present age so great and qualifies it as the best of all times is the combination of two factors: for one, never before in human history have technology and the natural sciences reached as high a level of development and have the average material living standards been as high as today – which appears essentially correct and which fact without doubt contributes greatly to the public appeal and acceptance of the Whig theory; and secondly, never before in history have people supposedly experienced as much freedom as today with the development of “liberal democracy” or “democratic capitalism” – which claim, despite its widespread popularity, I consider a historical myth and, since the degree of freedom and of economic and technological development are indeed positively correlated, leads me to the conclusion that average material living standards would have been even higher than they presently are if history only had taken a different course.
But before offering an alternative, grand revisionist historical narrative and indicating where Pinker and his ilk go off the rails with their Whiggish world history, a few remarks on the history of science are in order. Until relatively recently, the belief in a steady growth of science, if nothing else, has never been much in doubt – until the early 1960s, with the historian of science Thomas Kuhn and his book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Kuhn, in contrast to the orthodox Whig-ish view on the matter, portrayed the development of science not so much as a continuous march upward and into the light, but rather as a sequence of “paradigm shifts” that followed each other much like – directionless – one lady-fashion follows another. The book became a huge success and for quite some time Kuhn’s view became itself a widespread fashion in philosophical circles. Kuhn notwithstanding, however, I still regard the traditional view concerning the development of science as essentially correct. The central error of Kuhn’s as well as of many philosophers of science and, revealingly, expressed also again and again, for instance, by Sheldon Cooper, the super-science-nerd-theoretical-physicist-character in the hugely popular TV-series The Big-Bang Theory, lies in a fundamental misconception regarding the interrelationship between science on the one hand and engineering or technology on the other.
This is the popular misconception of regarding science as coming before, having priority, and assuming a higher rank and dignity vis-à-vis engineering and technology, as only secondary and inferior intellectual enterprises, i.e. as mere “applied” science. In fact, however, matters are exactly the other way around. What comes methodologically first, and what makes science as we know it at all possible and at the same time provides its ultimate foundation, is human engineering and construction. Put plainly and bluntly: Without such purposefully designed and constructed instruments such as measuring rods, clocks, planes, rectangles, scales, counters, lenses, microscopes, telescopes, audiometers, thermometers, spectrometers, x-ray and ultrasound machines, particle accelerators, and on and on, no empirical and experimental science as we know it would be possible.
Or to put it in the words of the great late German philosopher-scientist Peter Janich: “Handwerk” comes before and provides the stable foundation and groundwork of “Mundwerk.” Whatever controversies or quibbles scientists may have, they are always controversies and quibbles within a stable operational framework and reference system defined by a given state of technology. And in the field of human engineering, no one would ever throw out or “falsify” a working instrument until and unless he had another, better working instrument available.
Hence, it is engineering and advances in engineering that make science and scientific progress possible and at the same time prevent that from happening, which Karl Popper’s “falsificationist” philosophy of science that currently dominates intellectual public opinion must admit as “always possible”: not only scientific regression but even the complete breakdown of our entire system of knowledge due to the supposedly “always possible” falsification of even its seemingly most basic hypotheses. What prevents this nightmare from happening and what exposes both Kuhn’s relativism and Popper’s related falsificationism as involving an elementary methodological error is the existence of “Handwerk” and its methodical priority and primacy over the mere “Mundwerk” of science.1
With this out of the way, I can now turn to the fake part of the Whig theory of history – concerning social history. While it is comparatively easy to diagnose technological and along with this also scientific progress: progress occurs, whenever we learn how to successfully accomplish some additional, more and/or quicker or better result in our purposeful dealings with the non-human world of material objects, plants and animals; – it is significantly more difficult to define and diagnose social progress, i.e. progress in inter-personal dealings or man-to-man interactions.
To do this, it is first necessary to define a model of social perfection that is in accordance with human nature, i.e. of men as they really are, which can serve as a reference system to diagnose the relative proximity or distance of various historical events, periods and developments to and from this ideal. And this definition of social perfection and social progress must be strictly separate, independent and analytically distinct from the definition of technological and scientific growth and perfection (even if both progress- or growth-dimensions are empirically positively correlated). Conceptually, that is, it must be allowed that there can be societies that are (near) perfect socially but technologically backward as well as societies that are technologically highly advanced and yet socially backward.
For the libertarian, this ideal of social perfection is peace, i.e. a normally tranquil and frictionless person-to-person interaction – and a peaceful resolution of occasional conflict – within the stable framework of private or several (mutually exclusive) property and property rights. I do not want to appeal with this only libertarians, however, but a potentially universal or “catholic” audience, because the same ideal of social perfection is essentially also the one prescribed by the ten biblical commandments.
Setting the first four commandments aside, which refer to our relation to God as the one and only ultimate moral authority and final judge of our earthly conduct and the proper celebration of the Sabbath, the rest, referring to worldly affairs, display a deep and profoundly libertarian spirit.
5. Honor your father and your mother, as the LORD your God has commanded you, that your days may be long, and that it may be well with you in the land which the LORD your God is giving you.
6. You shall not murder.
7. You shall not commit adultery.
8. You shall not steal.
9. You shall not bear false witness against your neighbor.
10. You shall not covet your neighbor’s wife; and you shall not desire your neighbor’s house, his field, his male servant, his female servant, his ox, his donkey, or anything that is your neighbor’s.
Some libertarians may argue that not all of these commandments have the same rank or status. They may point out, for instance, that the fifth and the seventh commandment are not on a par and of the same dignity as the commandments six, eight and ten; that this may also be the case with commandment nine, prohibiting libel; or that desiring another’s wife or servant is not on a par with coveting his house or field. However, the ten commandments do not say anything about the severity and suitable punishment of violations of its various commands. They proscribe all mentioned activities and desires, but they leave open the question of how severely any of them deserves to be punished.
In this, the biblical commandments go above and beyond what many libertarians regard as sufficient for the establishment of a peaceful social order: the mere strict adherence to the commandments six, eight and ten. Yet this difference between a strict and rigid libertarianism and the ten biblical commandments does not imply any incompatibility of the two. Both are in complete harmony if only a distinction is made between legal prohibitions on the one hand, expressed in the commandments six, eight and ten, violations of which may be punished by the exercise of physical violence, and extra-legal or moral prohibitions on the other hand, expressed in the commandments five, seven and nine, violations of which may be punished only by means below the threshold of physical violence, such as social disapproval, discrimination, exclusion or ostracism. Indeed, thus interpreted the full six mentioned commandments can be recognized as even an improvement over a strict and rigid libertarianism – given the common, shared goal of social perfection: of a stable, just and peaceful social order.
For surely, any society of people who habitually disrespect their parents and routinely mock the idea of natural ranks and hierarchies of social authority, which underlies the institution of the family; who pooh-pooh the institution of marriage and cavalierly regard adultery as inconsequential, fault-less, or even liberating acts; or who habitually scoff at the idea of personal honor and honesty and routinely or even gleefully engage in libelous activity, i.e. the practice of “bearing false witness against one’s neighbor” – any such society will quickly disintegrate into a group of people ceaselessly disturbed by social strife and conflict rather than enjoying enduring and lasting peace.
Taking this biblical-libertarian ideal of social perfection as a benchmark, then, the next step in our argument must be the diagnosis, i.e. the comparative evaluation and ranking of various historical periods and developments regarding their relative proximity or distance to this ultimate, ideal goal.
In this regard, immediately a first diagnosis concerning the contemporary world impresses itself. Even if we may grant that the dominant Western model of “liberal democracy” or “democratic capitalism” comes closer to the ideal than the models of social organization presently followed elsewhere, outside the so-called Western world, it still falls glaringly short of the ideal. Indeed, it explicitly and unequivocally contradicts and violates the “catholic” biblical commandments, and the proponents and promoters of this model, then, manifestly (even if not admittedly so) deny and oppose God’s will and turn out advocates of the devil instead.
For one, even with the greatest intellectual contortions it is impossible to derive the institution of a State from these commandments. If no one may steal, murder or desire another person’s property, then no institution that may steal, murder and desire another person’s property can ever be permitted to come into existence. Yet as all other societies today, all present Western societies, too, are societies with States, which may routinely steal (tax), murder (go to war) and covet other people’s property (legislate). Moreover, in Western democratic-State-societies in particular, the moral sin of desiring another man’s property is not only not strictly and universally out-lawed (but routinely put in practice), but under democracy this sin is actually promoted and “cultivated” to its utmost – devilish – extreme. With democratic elections installed as the centerpiece of social life, everyone is “liberated” from God’s commandment and made “free” to desire whatever he wants of the property of others and to express his immoral desires through regular anonymous votes.
Surely, this liberal-democratic model of social organization cannot be the end of history, neither for a libertarian nor anyone taking the biblical commandments to heart. Indeed, Fukuyama’s claim to the contrary borders on the blasphemous.
Regardless of how disastrous the diagnosis of the contemporary world turns out to be, however, it might still be the case that the present state of affairs represents some sort of progress. It might not be the end of history, but it might be a closer approximation to the goal of social perfection than anything historically preceding it. To refute the Whig theory of history in its entirety, then, it is further necessary to identify some earlier (and thus, naturally, technologically less advanced) society that adhered more closely to the biblical commandments and came nearer to social perfection. And so as to carry any weight in public debate (in the battle of rival historical narratives), the counter-example in question should be a ‘big’ one. That is, it should not be some tiny place for only a short time span, but a large-scale and long-lasting historical phenomenon. And for the same reason of potential popular appeal, the example should be connected, both geographically and genealogically, as a historical predecessor to the contemporary Western model of democratic State-societies, and it should not lie too far in the dark and distant past.
In my own attempts at offering a revisionist account of Western history – in particular in my two books Democracy. The God That Failed and A Short History of Man – I have identified the European Middle Ages or what is sometimes also and better referred to as Latin Christendom, the roughly thousand-year period from the fall of Rome until the late 16th or early 17th century, as such an example. Not perfect in many ways, but closer to the ideal of social perfection than anything that followed it and in particular the present democratic order.
Not surprisingly, this is also the very period in Western history that our current – Godless – democratic rulers and their court historians have chosen to portray in the darkest of terms. In Greek and Roman society, they can see some “good” and valuable, even if it supposedly lags far behind the level of social advancement reached with the contemporary democratic social order. But as for the Middle Ages, they are routinely portrayed as dark, cruel, and filled with superstition, best to be forgotten and ignored in all of standard history and historical narrative.
Why this most unfavorable treatment in particular of the Middle Ages? Because, as many historians, old and contemporary, have of course noticed, too, the Middle Ages represent a large-scale and long-lasting historical example of a State-less society and as such represent the polar opposite of the present, Statist social order. Indeed, the Middle Ages, notwithstanding its many imperfections, can be identified as a God-pleasing – a “gott-gefaellige” – social order, whereas the present democratic State-order, notwithstanding its numerous achievements, stands in constant violation of God’s commandments and must be identified as a satanic order. And to answer the question then, Satan and his earthly followers will of course go all-out to make us ignore and forget about God and belittle, besmirch and denigrate everything and anything that shows his hands.
The more reason for any libertarian and God-pleasing ‘catholic’ to study and draw inspiration from this historical period of the European Middle Ages – something, incidentally, made easier nowadays and likely to encounter little opposition from the powers-that-be and their increasingly rigorously enforced speech-code of “political correctness,” because any such study has long since been relegated to the status of a nerdy, quaint and exotic interest, far distant in time from the present and without any contemporary relevance.
In standard (orthodox) history we are told, as a quasi-axiomatic truth, that the institution of a State is necessary and indispensable for the maintenance of social peace. The study of the Middle Ages and Latin Christendom shows that this is untrue, a historical myth, and how, for a lengthy historical period, peace was successfully maintained without a State and thus without open renunciation of libertarian and biblical precepts.
While many libertarians fancy an anarchic social order as a largely horizontal order without hierarchies and different ranks of authority – as “anti-authoritarian” – the medieval example of a State-less society teaches otherwise. Peace was not maintained by the absence of hierarchies and ranks of authority, but by the absence of anything but social authority and ranks of social authority. Indeed, in contrast to the present order, which essentially recognizes only one authority, that of the State, the Middle Ages were characterized by a great multitude of competing, cooperating, overlapping and hierarchically ordered ranks of social authority. There was the authority of the heads of family households and of various kinship groups. There were patrons, lords, overlords and feudal kings with their estates, and their vassals, and the vassals of vassals. There were countless different and separate communities and towns, and a huge variety of religious, artistic, professional and social orders, councils, assemblies, guilds, associations and clubs, each with their own rules, hierarchies and rank orders. In addition, and of utmost importance, there were the authorities of the local priest, the more distant bishop, and of the Pope in Rome.
But no authority was absolute, and no one or no one group of people held a monopoly on its position or rank of authority. The hierarchical feudal lord-vassal relationship, for instance, was not indissoluble. It could be broken if either side violated the provisions of the fealty-oaths they both had sworn to uphold. Nor was the relationship between lord and vassal a transitive one. That is, the lord of a vassal was not on account of his lordship also the lord of all his vassal’s vassals. Indeed, such vassals could be tied as vassals to a different lord, or they could, elsewhere and regarding other things, be a lord themselves that precluded any involvement in the affairs of the very lord in question. It was thus near-impossible for anyone to exercise any straight top-down authority and hence made also immensely difficult in particular to raise and maintain a large standing army and engage in large-scale or even continent-wide war. That is, the phenomenon which we have come to regard as perfectly normal today, that a command is given from the top on down that is directly binding on all of society, from its highest ranks down to the lowliest, was absent in the Middle Ages. Authority was widely dispersed, and any one person or position of authority was constrained and kept in check by another. Even feudal kings, bishops, and indeed even the Pope himself could be called upon and brought to justice by other, competing authorities.
“Feudal Law” reflected this “hierarchic-anarchic” social structure of the Middle Ages. All of law was essentiallyprivate law, i.e. law applying to persons and person-to-person interactions, all of litigation was between a personal defendant and a personal plaintiff, and punishment typically involved the payment of some specified material compensation by the offender to his victim or his lawful successor. However, this central characteristic of the Middle Ages as a historical model of a private law society did not mean that feudal law was some sort of unitary, coherent and consistent legal system. To the contrary, feudal law allowed for a great variety of locally and regionally different laws and customs, and the difference in the treatment of similar offences in different localities could be quite drastic. Yet at the same time, with the Catholic Church and the Scholastic teachings of the Natural Law, there was an over-arching institutional framework and moral reference system in place to serve as a morally unifying force, constraining and moderating the range of variation between the laws of different localities.
Needless to say, there were many imperfections that future historians, up to this day, would focus on and highlight so as to discredit the entire period. During the Middle Ages, under the influence of Catholic Church, the institution of slavery, which had been a dominant feature of Greek and Roman society, had been increasingly discredited and pushed back to near extinction, but it had not entirely disappeared. As well, the institution of serfdom, from a moral point of view “better” than slavery but still not without moral blemish, was still a widespread social phenomenon. Moreover, plenty of small-scale wars and feuds took place during the entire period. And as we are never allowed to forget: The punishments dished out in various law courts for various offences here or there, were sometimes (for modern sensibilities in any case) extreme, harsh and cruel. A murderer might be hung, or beheaded, quartered, burnt, boiled or drowned. A thief might have his finger or hand cut off, and a false witness his tongue torn out. An adulteress might be stoned, a rapist castrated, and a “witch” burnt.
It is these features in particular that we are told in standard history to associate with the Middle Ages so as to arouse our moral indignation and feel elated about our own enlightened present. Even if all true, however, any such exclusive concentration on these features as a distinctive characteristic of the Middle Ages is to miss the mark, or the wood for the trees. It takes accidents for nature and what is natural and normal. That is, it ignores, whether deliberately or not, the central characteristic of the entire period: the fact that it was a State-less social order with widely dispersed, hierarchically ordered and rivaling centers of authority. And it then conveniently closes the eyes to the fact that the “excesses” of the Middle Ages actually pale in comparison to those of the present democratic State order.
For surely, slavery and serfdom have not disappeared in the democratic world. Rather, some increasingly rare ‘private’ slavery and serfdom have been replaced by a near-universal system of ‘public’ tax-slavery and serfdom. As well, wars have not disappeared, but only become of a larger scale. And as for excessive punishments and witch hunts, they have not gone away either. To the contrary, they have multiplied. Enemies of the State are tortured in the same old gruesome or even technically ‘refined’ ways. Moreover, countless people who are not a murderer, a thief, a libeler, an adulterer or a rapist, i.e. people who live in complete accordance with the ten biblical commandments and once would have been left alone, are nonetheless routinely punished today, up to the level of lengthy incarceration or the loss of their entire property. Witches are no longer called that way, but with just one single authority in place, the “identification” of anyone as a “suspect of evil-doing” or a “trouble-maker” is greatly facilitated and the number of people so identified has accordingly multiplied; and while such suspects are no longer burnt at the stake, they are routinely punished by up to life-long economic deprivation, unemployment, poverty or even starvation. And while once, during the Middle Ages, the primary purpose of punishment was restitution, i.e. the offender had to compensate the victim, the primary purpose of punishment today is submission, i.e. the offender must compensate and satisfy not the victim but the State (thus victimizing the victim twice).
With this we can state a first conclusion. The present democratic social order may be the technologically most advanced civilization, but it most certainly is not the socially most advanced. As measured by biblical-libertarian standards of social perfection it falls far behind the Middle Ages. Indeed, as measured by those standards, the transition in European history from the anarchic medieval to the modern Statist world is nothing less than the transition from a God-pleasing to a God-less social order.
At various places, in the most condensed form in my essay From Aristocracy to Monarchy to Democracy, I have analyzed and tried to reconstruct this process of de-civilization, which has by now been going on for half a millennium, and to explain the calamitous and deleterious consequences and ramifications that it has had for the development of law and economics. I shall not repeat or recapitulate any of this here. Rather, I only want to shed some light on the principal strategy that all Statists, from the late Middle Ages on until today, have pursued to reach their Statist ends, so as to also gain (if only indirectly) some insight into any possible counter-strategy that could lead us out of the current predicament. Not back to the Middle Ages, of course, because too many permanent and irreversible changes have taken place since, both in regard to our mental and our material conditions and capacities. But to a new society that takes its cues from the study of the Middle Ages and understands and knows of the principal reason for its demise.
The strategy was dictated by the quasi-libertarian, State-less medieval starting point, and it suggested itself ‘naturally’ first and foremost to the top ranks of social authority, i.e. in particular to feudal kings. In a nutshell, it boils down to this rule: Instead of remaining a mere primus inter pares you must become a solus primus, and to do this you must undermine, weaken and ultimately eliminate all competing authorities and hierarchies of social authority. Beginning at the highest levels of authority, with your most immediate competitors, and from there on down ultimately to the most elementary and decentralized level of social authority invested in the heads of individual family households, you (every Statist) must use your own initial authority to undermine each and every rival authority and strip away its right to independently judge, discriminate, sentence and punish within its own territorially limited realm of authority.
Kings other than you must no longer be allowed to freely determine who is another or the next king, who is to be included or excluded from the rank of kings, or who may or may not come before them for justice and assistance. And likewise for all other levels of social authority, for noble lords and vassals as well as all separate local communities, orders, associations and ultimately all individual family households. No one must be free to autonomously determine its own rules of admission and exclusion. That is: to determine who is supposed to be ‘in’ or ‘out,’ what conduct to expect of those who are ‘in’ and want to remain in good standing, and what membership conduct instead results in various sanctions, ranging from disapproval, censure and fines to expulsion and corporal punishment.
And how to accomplish this and centralize and consolidate all authority in the hands of a single territorial monopolist, first an absolute monarch and subsequently a democratic State? By enlisting the support of everyone resentful of not being included or promoted in some particular community, association or social rank, or for being expelled from them and ‘unfairly’ punished. Against this ‘unfair discrimination’ you, the State or would-be State, promise the excluded ‘victims’ to get them ‘in’ and help them get a ‘fair’ and ‘non-discriminating’ treatment in return for their binding commitment to and affiliation with you. On every level of social authority, whenever and wherever the opportunity arises, you encourage and promote ‘deviant behavior’ and ‘deviants’ and enlist their support in order to expand and strengthen your own authority at the expense of all others.
Accordingly, the principal counter-strategy of re-civilization, then, must be a return to ‘normality’ by means of de-centralization. The process of territorial expansion that went hand in hand with the centralization of all authority in one monopolistic hand must be reversed. Each and every secessionist tendency and movement, then, should be supported and promoted, because with every territorial separation from the central State is another, separate and rival center of authority and adjudication created. And the same tendency should be promoted within the framework of any newly created separate and independent territory and center of authority. That is, any voluntary membership organization, association, order, club or even household within the new territory should be free to independently determine its own house-rules, i.e. its rules of inclusion, of sanctions and of exclusion, so as to successively replace the current Statist system of forced territorial and legal integration and uni-formation with a natural, quasi-organic social order of voluntary territorial and legal-customary association and dis-association. Moreover, as an important addition: In order to safeguard this order of increasingly decentralized centers, ranks and hierarchies of natural social authority from internal corruption or external (foreign) attack, each newly (re)emerging social authority should be encouraged to build as wide as possible a network with similarly placed and like-minded authorities in other, ‘foreign’ territories and jurisdictions for the purpose of mutual assistance in case of need.
*
With this I have reached a stage of conceptual analysis and of historical insight and background information that allows me, as my second task, to comment in some detail on the most recent attempt by Steven Pinker, with his book The Better Angels of Our Nature, to give new impetus to the Whig theory of history, i.e. the myth that human history has been a somewhat rocky but nonetheless steady march upward and into the light and that we today, in the Western world, live if not in the best of all possible worlds but a world better than anything that came before.
The book, unsurprisingly, has been enthusiastically greeted by the ruling elites and become a great commercial success, further boosted undoubtedly by Pinker’s status as a charismatic Harvard professor. On 800 pages of small print, the book assembles a huge mass of interesting pieces of information and interpretation concerning all sorts of things, but insofar as the case made therein of Pinker’s central thesis of some steady social progress culminating in the present, my verdict is entirely negative. Pinker may be an excellent psychologist, but he is out of his depth in the areas of philosophy, methodology, economics and history, which all are required to pass sound judgment on the degree of social perfection of the various stages and long-run development of human history. In particular, his historical narratives frequently strike one as cherry-picking and either missing the wood for the trees or vice versa, and more often, the trees for the wood.2
There is plenty to complain about the book, not least the fact that Pinker is less than careful in unambiguously defining his terms so as to avoid all internal inconsistency or equivocation. Here, however, I shall concentrate my criticism on only two central points. First, Pinker’s “measurement” or criterion of social progress – his explanandum – and then his explanation for the so “measured” phenomenon – his explanans.
Throughout his entire work, Pinker shows a remarkable hostility to religion and hence it is hardly surprising that it does not cross his mind to use the biblical commandments (which he incidentally grossly misrepresents) as benchmark for social perfection. Rather, his benchmark is “violence,” and social progress is defined as a reduction in violence. At first sight, this criterion does not seem too far away from the biblical-libertarian goal of peace. In fact, however, it turns out to be something quite different. His prime examples of violence are homicides and war casualties. The book is filled with tables and statistics on such indicators of violence. Incredibly, however, Pinker does not make a categorical distinction between aggressive and defensive violence. In the biblical commandments with their explicit recognition of the sanctity of private property, such a distinction is made. It makes a difference if violence is used to take another man’s property, or if a man uses violence in defense of his property against an aggressor. Murder is a categorically different thing than the killing of someone in self-defense.
Not so for Pinker.
Property and property rights do not systematically figure in his analyses. Indeed, the terms do not even appear in the book’s 30-page subject index. For Pinker, violence is violence, and the reduction of violence is progress, regardless of whether this reduction is the result of the successful suppression and resignation of a people by and vis-à-vis another, conquering people, or the result of a people’s own successful suppression of aggressors and conquerors.
In Pinker’s world, a ‘stable’ master-slave relationship is a sign of civilization, while a slave-revolt accompanied by violence is a sign of de-civilization. Likewise, a system of compulsory taxation – another term which like that of property is completely missing in the index (not coincidentally) – and regardless of the height of taxation is an indicator of civilization as long as it is only stable, i.e. as long as the mere threat of punishment by the tax-authority is sufficient to result in general compliance on the part of the taxed, whereas any tax-revolt and resistance is to count as de-civilization. One is peace and progress to Pinker, whereas the other is violence and regression.
Pinker does not follow his own logic to the bitter end, but it deserves to be pointed out to reveal the full depravity of his thought. According to him, a smoothly run concentration camp, for instance, guarded by armed men who do not murder the inmates and prevent them from killing each other, but who supply them with “happiness drugs” to keep them quietly working on for the benefit of the guards until their natural (non-violent) deaths, is the perfect model of peace and social progress, while the violent overthrow of the guards by the concentration camp inmates is, well, violence and de-civilization.
Based on this depraved view of social progress that knows of no property and property rights violations but only counts the number of unnatural deaths, bodily injuries and broken bones, it should be expected that Pinker’s evaluations of various historical episodes must yield some rather awkward or even grotesque conclusions, as in fact they do. In particular, it also explains how Pinker could possibly mis-represent the present democratic age as the best of all times.
But is it, even on Pinker’s own terms? Are we living today in the least violent of times?
The answer is ambiguous. On the one hand there are wars, which throughout history have always been responsible for the largest number of casualties, far outweighing those resulting from ‘regular’ small-scale interpersonal violence. In this regard, as Nicholas Taleb has shown in response to Pinker’s progression thesis, no statistically discernable trend can be established. According to Taleb, for the 600-year period from about 1500 until today, for which we have relatively reliable data, no significant change as to the frequency of war or the number of war-casualties (always set in relation to the total population) can be made out. Indeed, if anything there has been a slight uptick in war-related violence with the spread of democracy (contrary to the proponents of the so-called democratic-peace theory). And as for the 70-year period since the end of World War II until today, which Pinker identifies as exceptionally peaceful and war-less, Taleb points out that wars and especially large-scale wars are highly irregular and comparatively rare events and that an observation period of just 70 years, then, is far too short to serve as the basis for any far-reaching conclusions.
As well, as John Gray has argued contra Pinker, even this assessment of “modern times” is likely too rosy a picture, because it tends to systematically underestimate the number of war-related casualties among non-combatants, i.e. the number of civilians dying from various diseases spread through war or from long-term side-effects of war such as “slow deaths” caused by economic deprivation and starvation. (The same danger of underestimation does not exist, at least not to the same extent, for the wars of the European Middle Ages, because they were typically small-scale, territorially restricted events and involved a comparatively sharp distinction and separation between and of combatants and non-combatants.)
On the other hand, there exists indeed plenty of empirical evidence to speak of a supra-secular trend toward a reduction in violence – not to be confused with a reduction in the infringements on property rights – as measured in particular by homicide rates (a homicide is a homicide regardless of who kills whom, why or how). In this extra- or a-moral sense, we can indeed speak of a “civilizing process,” as Pinker does and demonstrates in great detail. Pinker adopts this term from Norbert Elias and his book The Civilizing Process, first published in German in 1939 and translated into English 30 years later. In this book, Elias describes and aims to explain the changes in everyday etiquette, from table-manners to sexual mores, that occurred during and since the European Middles Ages. Put briefly, this process can be described as the gradual transition from brutish, gross, crude, boorish, bearish, immodest and intemperate, etc. pp, behavior to increasingly more refined, controlled, considerate, modest and temperate, etc. pp, human conduct. Taking his cues from Elias, Pinker merely generalizes and expands Elias’s civilizing thesis from human etiquette to all of everyday life and behavior – and in this, in my judgment, he is by and large successful.
However, Pinker’s explanation for this extra- or a-moral form of social progress from brutish to increasingly refined behavior is fundamentally mistaken. What he identifies as the principal cause of this development, and I will come to his cause in a moment, has actually, if anything, retarded and distorted this development. That is, absent Pinker’s cause, there would have been not less but more (and a significantly different) refinement in human conduct.
In fact, the grand, long-run historical tendency toward increasingly more refined (or less brutish) behavior can be explained, simple enough, as the quasi-natural by-product of the widening and deepening of the division of labor in the course of economic and technological development. The development of increasingly more and different productivity-enhancing tools and instruments proceeded hand in hand with the development and increasing differentiation of human crafts, skills and talents. Put briefly, the importance of muscle power for economic success declined relative to the importance of brain power, physical finesse and mental agility. Moreover, as I have tried to explain in my A Short History of Man, especially under Malthusian conditions, which prevailed for most of human history, a systematic premium for economic success and indeed human survival is placed on the progressive development and growth of human intelligence, of low time-preference, impulse control and patience (which personal characteristics are at least partially hereditary and thus passed on through subsequent generations).
Pinker’s explanation for this tendency toward a progressive refinement of human conduct is a very different one, however. His explanation for this development is the institution of a State, i.e. a territorial monopolist of ultimate decision-making; and he claims that the most decisive and all-important step in the progressive refinement of human conduct has been the transition from a State-less social order to a Statist society. And in this he is not entirely wrong – given that his definition of progressive refinement is an extra- or a-moral one. Certainly, the institution of States, and more specifically of democratic States, is the principal cause of many central features and observations concerning our present-day human conduct and routines – except to notice that many or most of them have little or nothing to do with moral progress and stand in open contradiction to biblical commandments. As well, violence as defined by Pinker may indeed have gone down – except to notice that the exercise of violence has been so ‘refined’ and re-defined under State-auspices as to no longer fall under Pinker’s narrow definition of the term. “Witches,” for instance, are no longer violently burnt, but shipped off instead, seemingly peacefully, into psychiatric wards to be drugged and pacified by medical professionals; and neighbors are no longer robbed of their property violently, but, much ‘refined’ and apparently without any physical violence, presented with regularly recurring tax-bills to be quasi-automatically paid per bank transfer into the accounts of the State.
The central cause identified by Pinker for social progress and increasing social perfection, then, the institution of a State, actually turns out a central force of de-civilization, retarding and distorting the underlying civilizing process naturally set in motion with the deepening and widening of the division of labor in the course of economic development. The institution of the State may explain the refinement of violence in the course of time, but it is itself a constant source of violence, however refined, and the driving force for its expansion and intensification. The subtitle of Pinker’s book, Why Violence Has Declined, would lead most potential readers to expect an answer to a moral question or problem, because of the negative connotations typically associated with the term violence. Yet as such the book’s title is an ingenious attempt at false and deceptive advertisement, because Pinker does nothing of the sort. Instead, he answers the very different question of how to ‘technically’ or ‘scientistically’ define violence so as to make the morally most depraved and violent institution of all appear as a peacemaker, or to make Satan look like an angel.
And how does he do this? First, in throwing out logic and plain common sense and then fudging the data and historical narratives so as to fit his plain nonsensical basic premise. This basic premise is presented by Pinker in the form of a simple diagram (p. 35). In any two-person scenario, both parties may have a motive for violence, either as an aggressor to prey on the other or as a victim to retaliate. Consequently, similar to Hobbes, Pinker pictures this state of affairs as one of interminable violent conflict, as a bellum omnium contra omnes, a war of all against all. But miraculously, there is a cure to this problem, a third party, called bystander by Pinker, that acts as judge and assumes the role as a territorial monopolist of violence so as create lasting peace. – But would this bystander not also be a potential predator? And would his predator motives not be even strengthened, if he were the monopolist of violence and did not have to fear any retaliation from his victims? Pinker does not address these rather obvious questions let alone provide a systematic answer to them.
Nor does he provide an answer to the question why anyone would submit himself, without resistance, to any such by-standing monopolistic judge. Would no one recognize the potential danger for his own property from such an arrangement and put up resistance against its establishment? To be sure, Pinker cannot escape to later on notice that empirically, States qua territorial monopolists of violence did not emerge spontaneously or quasi-organically, but mafia-like as some sort of protection rackets. Yet this observation does not lead him to revise or reject his fundamental thesis about the principal role of the State as a peacemaker, nor does it lead him to the recognition that many if not most of the civilizing achievements that he ascribes to the workings of the State are in fact the results of popular resistance against State-power, whether active and violent or passive and non-violent. Indeed, as mentioned before, Pinker classifies any violent resistance against the State as de-civilization, which implies that the prior violence exercised by the State vis-à-vis the resister must have been a civilizing and pacifying activity, not to be counted as violence at all; and almost needless to say then that such mental acrobatics cannot but lead to various contradictions from which Pinker can extricate himself only through more or less ingenious but always intellectually painful contortions.
Pinker’s identification of the State as the all-important force in the process of civilization coincides of course perfectly well with the assessment of all State-rulers everywhere, and it is essentially the very same lesson that we all have been taught in school and university to accept as a quasi-axiomatic truth. In particular, it is the same lesson taught also by all contemporary “leading economists.” And yet, it flatly contradicts one of the most elementary laws of economics: Production under monopolistic conditions will lead to higher prices and lower quality of whatever is produced as compared to the production of the same product under competitive conditions, i.e. under conditions of “free entry.” Most contemporary economists recognize this law, but they fail to apply it to the peculiar monopoly that is the State – most likely because most of them are employed by the State. But in fact it applies to the State as well, regardless of how one describes the specific product produced by it. If we describe the State, as Pinker does, as a territorial monopolist of peace-making, then the peace made by it will be more expensive and of lower quality. If we describe it as a monopolist of justice, then justice will be of higher cost and of lower quality. If we describe it as a monopolist of violence, its violence will be more expensive and of worse quality. Or if we describe it, as I think best, as a territorial monopolist of expropriation charged with the task of property protection, then we will predictably get much expropriation, which benefits the monopolist, and little protection, which will be only costly for the State. In any case, the result is always the same, and Pinker’s central thesis concerning the civilizing effect of the institution of a State, then, must be rejected on logical grounds alone.
What about Pinker’s empirical case, then? Logic cannot be refuted by empirical data, but if one throws out logic one is bound to misinterpret empirical data. Pinker offers a huge number of empirical data, tables and graphs of great interest. I have quarrels with some of them, but here I accept them all for the sake of argument. My criticism concerns solely his interpretation of these data. In fact, and as mentioned before, I can largely go along with his generalized Elias-thesis about a civilizing process from brutish to refined human conduct. Based on logic, however, I would interpret it differently. Whatever civilizing process there is, it did not occur because of the State, but despite of or in resistance against the State; and whatever de-civilizing process there is, it did not occur because of the absence of a State, but in spite of its absence, or as the late, on-lingering effect of a prior (now dissolved) State and its earlier de-civilizing tendencies. Post-hoc does not imply propter hoc.
I will restrict my criticism to two central exhibits that Pinker offers in empirical support of his thesis. One concerning global affairs, and another regionally more specific one that is most directly related to my earlier observations on European or Western history.
The empirical support for the global progression thesis is summarized in two tables (p.49/53). The first is supposed to show the decline of war-deaths (as percentage of population) from human prehistory to the present. For this, Pinker distinguishes four historical stages: prehistory, hunter-gatherer societies, hunter-horticulturalist societies and finally State-societies. And he then provides data to show that there was at best only a minimal improvement from the highly violent prehistoric to the hunter-gatherer stage; that violence increased again with the introduction of horticulture and agriculture (as there is then more economic inequality and more to loot); and that it finally dropped off sharply to a level never seen before in human history with the introduction of State-societies. As well, to further bolster his thesis, the second table compares the rate of death in warfare for ‘modern’ non-State societies (of the 19th and 20th century) with equally ‘modern’ State-societies, demonstrating supposedly once more the civilizing effect of States.
;As said before, I shall not quibble about the numbers and estimates presented in these tables, except to note that any estimate concerning human prehistory and the far distant hunter-gatherer-horticulturalist stage(s) of human history must be viewed with a good dose of skepticism. Archeological findings of broken skulls, for instance, can provide the basis for some reasonable estimate of violence at particular places and times, and you may then also scale-up such estimates to the estimated total world population at the time to calculate the violent-death rate for any given time period. But what you cannot do and what is for rather obvious technical reasons and at least until today near-impossible to do, is to show that your sample of violence-data is a representative random sample, from which alone it would be legitimate to generalize one’s specific findings to the population total.
The central reason, however, why Pinker’s data fail to demonstrate what he wants to demonstrate is a different one. In his attempt to compare non-State societies with State-societies he is comparing what cannot be compared. His examples of non-State societies, whether ancient or modern, refer almost exclusively to some obscure tribes outside of Europe (or in a few rare European cases to tribes living thousands of years prior to the Christian era); and all of them have either literally died out or else left no lasting trace in history in that it is near impossible today to trace any one contemporary society genealogically back to them as their historical predecessor. In distinct contrast, all examples of State-societies are taken from Europe and the Western world, where such genealogical back-tracing is easily possible for periods of hundreds or even thousands of years. Obviously, such a comparison can yield an unbiased conclusion only under the assumption that the only relevant factor distinguishing European or “Western” people from Pinker’s various tribesmen is the presence vs. the absence of a State; and that otherwise both people are the same, made up of the same physical and mental constitution and endowment.
Pinker never explicitly states this for his own case crucial assumption. Probably, because this would cast some immediate doubt on the validity of his conclusion. And indeed, as a matter of fact there are countless empirical studies in the meantime, in many disciplines, that demonstrate the utter falsehood of this assumption. Substantial differences exist in the physical and mental makeup and endowments of different people. Europeans or more generally “Westerners” are decidedly not the same sort of people that Pinker’s tribesmen are – and with that his first “empirical proof” of his progression thesis collapses. His proof is a non-starter and proves nothing.
In addition, Pinker misses the trees of humans for the global wood of mankind also in another regard; for according to his own data there are also some non-State societies, even if only a few, that equal or even surpass the level of peacefulness achieved in State-societies.
As a brief aside: Pinker might not even be aware of the fact that some sort of (false) human “equality” assumption is necessary to make his point, but he assumes it anyhow, again and again, if only implicitly or surreptitiously. Deep-down, Pinker is an egalitarian, as shows up in particular in his outspoken sympathy for the “progress” brought about by the so-called “civil rights movement” and the “noble” Dr. Martin Luther King as well as “one of history’s greatest statesmen,” Nelson Mandela (notwithstanding both men’s well-known communist connections). Pinker is not an extreme (and extremely silly) egalitarian, of course. He makes distinctions between sexes, ages, races and classes, and he is well aware of the unequal distribution of various human traits and talents within society, of intelligence, diligence, impulse-control, sociability, etc. But as a politically correct “progressive,” he cannot bring himself to the recognition that the unequal distribution of these human traits and talents within society may be a very different one in different societies.
With Pinker’s first, global empirical “proof” rejected, what about his second, regional one? Here, all data come from Europe and insofar the danger of comparing incompatibles is avoided. Pinker devotes some 10 pages (pp. 228-238) to this case, and the central information is condensed in a single graph (p. 230) depicting the “rate of death in conflicts in greater Europe, 1400-2000.” If anything, however, this graph demonstrates the opposite of Pinker’s progress thesis. What it shows is that the longest period of (relative) peacefulness and low levels of violence were the almost 200 years from 1400 until the very end of the 16th century. Yet this period falls precisely within the longer period of the European Middle Ages (and marks its end), and the Middle Ages, as I have argued before, are a prime example of a State-less social order. (Interestingly, Pinker concurs with this assessment of medieval Europe as State-less, but he then fails to see that this assessment implies, according to his own data, an empirical refutation of his thesis.)
And it gets worse for Pinker’s case. According to the same graph, the following historical period, from the late 16th century on to the present, is characterized by three huge spikes in the level of violence. The first spike, from the late 16th century until the Westphalian Peace in 1648, is largely associated with the 30-Years-War; the second, from the late 18th century until 1815 and somewhat less steep than the first, is associated with the French Revolution and the Napoleonic Wars; and the third and greatest spike, from 1914-1945, is associated with the 20th century’s two World Wars. As well, for all intermediate periods, the level of violence remained well above that of medieval times and this level was only reached again, three centuries later, during the period from 1815-1914, and again during the post-WW II era. All in all, then, the record for post-medieval Europe in terms of violence appears rather depressive. And yet, the entire period, from the late 16th century until today, is the era of States, which Pinker considers the driving forces of a “civilizing process.”
Pinker associates the first drastic spike in violence with religion and the “Wars of Religion.” In fact, however, they were wars to makes States. Feudal kings and princes aspiring to the rank of absolute ruler made war to bring increasingly larger contiguous territories under their supreme control. In this, they took advantage of the recent split within Latin Christendom of Catholics and Protestants, and it was they who actually invented the term “Wars of Religion” – if only so as to hide and deceive about their real purpose of State-making, which had little if anything to do with religion. The second spike marks the turning-point from monarchic to democratic States and is the result of Napoleonic France using war in the attempt of establishing hegemony over all of continental Europe. And the third and most drastic spike upward in the level of violence marks the beginning of the era of full-fledged democracy and is the result of Britain and the USA going to war to establish world-hegemony.
In his interpretation of these data, Pinker tries to make the best out of a (for him) rather desperate looking case. For one, he points out with the help of a second graph (p. 229), that throughout the entire period the number of violent conflicts declined as the number of States fell due to territorial consolidation and centralization. A greater number of small-scale wars with few casualties were replaced with a smaller number of large-scale wars with many casualties. This does not appear much like progress, however, especially if it is kept in mind that the rate of death in conflicts actually increased during the entire Statist era, even if the number of violent conflicts declined. To still rescue his progress-thesis, then, Pinker advances two auxiliary arguments. First, he claims that the more lethal character of (less frequent) modern wars has nothing to do with States per se or the territorial expansion and consolidation of States, but is instead the quasi-accidental result of advances in military technology (a thesis that he elsewhere rejects, when he states that the development of technology is essentially ‘neutral’ to the level of violence). And secondly, to add more weight to his thesis about the decline in the frequency of war (but not, to emphasize again, the decline of the war-related death-rate!), he points out that the process of political centralization, i.e. the increasingly smaller number of States with increasingly larger State-territories, was not accompanied by a corresponding increase of civil or intra-State war, and hence represents a real civilizing gain (and not just an accounting trick). Essentially, according to Pinker, with each political centralization and ultimately the establishment of a one-world-State the likelihood of war declines and ultimately disappears along with the parallel decline and disappearance of civil war. In short: States civilize and a one-world-State civilizes best. Or in reverse: each secession de-civilizes and complete freedom of secession de-civilizes most.
Economic logic (praxeology) dictates a very different interpretation of all this, however. States are not spontaneous, voluntary associations. They are the result of war. And the existence of States increases the likelihood of further wars, because under Statist conditions the cost of war-making must no longer be born privately but can at least partially be externalized onto innocent third parties. That the number of wars then declines as the number of States falls and that there can be no inter-State war once the number of States has been reduced to a single one-world-State is not much more than a definitional truth. Even if less frequent, however, the further advanced the process of political centralization and territorial consolidation, i.e. the closer to the ultimate Statist goal of a one-world-State, the more lethal such wars are to become.
Nor can the institution of a one-world-State deliver what Pinker promises. True, there can then be no inter-State wars, by definition. For the sake of argument, we may even concede that the frequency and the casualty rate of internal, civil wars may decline as well (although the empirical evidence for this appears increasingly doubtful). In any case, however, what can be safely predicted about the consequences of a one-world-State is this: With the removal of all inter-State competition, i.e. with the replacement of a multitude of different territorial jurisdictions with different laws, customs, tax- and regulation structures by a single, world-wide uniform jurisdiction, any possibility of voting with one’s feet against a State and its laws is removed as well. Hence, a fundamentally important constraint on the growth and expansion of State-power is gone, and the cost of the production of justice (or whatever it is that the State claims to produce) will accordingly rise to unprecedented heights, while its quality will reach a new low. There may or may not be less of the broken-bones type violence a la Pinker, but in any case there will be more ‘refined’ violence, i.e. property rights violations that do not count as violence for Pinker, than ever before; and the one-world-State society, then, will look more like the stable concentration camp scenario mentioned earlier than anything resembling a free, convivial social order.
Stripped down to its bare bones Pinker’s central argument amounts to a string of logical absurdities: According to him, tribal societies somehow “merge” to form small States and small States successively “coalesce” into increasingly larger States. If this “merging” and “coalescing” were, as the terms insinuate, a spontaneous and voluntary matter, however, the result, by definition, would not be a State but an anarchic social order composed of and governed by free membership associations. If, on the other hand, this “merging” and “coalescing” results instead in a State, it cannot be a spontaneous and voluntary matter but must, of logical necessity, involve violence and war (in that any territorial monopolization of whatever it is that is monopolized necessitates the violently enforced prohibition of “free entry”). But how, then, can anyone such as Pinker, who wants to reduce violence and war to a minimum and possibly eliminate it entirely, prefer a social system, any system, that necessitates the exercise of violence and war to a system that does not do so? Answer: Only in throwing out all of logic and claiming that the relationship between State and violence and war is not a logically necessary one, but a merely contingent, empirical relationship instead; that just as it is indeed an entirely empirical matter whether or not you or I commit violence and go to war, so it is also a purely contingent, empirical matter whether or not a State commits violence and goes to war.
Thus, according to Pinker, WW II with all its atrocities, for instance, had essentially nothing to do with the institution of States but was a historical fluke, owing to the evildoings of a single, deranged individual, Adolf Hitler. Indeed, unbelievably and seemingly without blushing (although that is admittedly difficult to tell from a written text) Pinker approvingly quotes historian John Keegan saying that “only one European really wanted war – Adolf Hitler.” (p.208)
Question: But how much evil can a single, deranged individual do without the institution of a centralized State? How much evil could Hitler have done within the framework of a State-less society such as the Middle Ages? Would he have become a great lord, a king, a bishop, or a Pope? Indeed, how much evil could he have done even within the framework of a thousand mini-States, such as Liechtenstein, Monaco or Singapore? Answer: Not much, and certainly nothing comparable to the evils associated with WW II. It holds not, then: ‘no Hitler, no Churchill, no Roosevelt or no Stalin, and then no war,’ as Pinker would have it, but rather: ‘no highly centralized State, and then no Hitler, Churchill, Roosevelt or Stalin.’
Remove the State, and they may have become a Jack the Ripper, a Charles Ponzi or even harmless people, but not the mass-murdering monsters we know them to be. Institute the State, and you create, attract and breed monsters.
In sum, then: Pinker’s attempt to rescue the Whig theory of history and demonstrate that we live in the best of all worlds turns out an utter failure. Indeed, one may even say that his book and its great commercial success is itself empirical proof of the contrary.
Presented to The Property and Freedom Society, September 16th, 2018
- 1.Note: I am not denying here the possibility of periods of regression in the development of science. But I would explain any such regression as the consequence of a prior loss of practical engineering knowledge. ‘Harmlessly,’ in the normal course of economic development, certain skills may die out and be forgotten, because there is no longer any demand for their products. This does not necessarily imply a step back in engineering knowledge, however. Indeed, such loss can be more than made up by the development of different skills, required for the manufacturing of different, more highly demanded products. Loss here is the springboard of technological progress. Old tools and machines are replaced by better new ones. But another, less ‘harmless’ development is possible as well and has indeed taken place at certain times and places. Due to a pestilence, for instance, the population size, and with this also the division of labor, might dramatically shrink and lead to a huge and widespread loss of accumulated engineering knowledge and skills, so as to require a return to earlier and more primitive modes of production. Or else, a population might simply become less bright, for whatever reason, than its forebears and unable to maintain a given (inherited) level of technological advancement.
- 2.See on the following also Stefan Blankertz, https://www.lewrockwell.com/2018/05/no_author/pinker-versus-anarchy-are-tyrants-the-lesser-evil/
Comments on this entry are closed.